Free Capitalist Network - Community Archive
Mises Community Archive
An online community for fans of Austrian economics and libertarianism, featuring forums, user blogs, and more.

Voting: Constitutional Amendments and Propositions?

rated by 0 users
This post has 3 Replies | 2 Followers

Not Ranked
Posts 28
Points 650
David Posted: Sun, Oct 3 2010 12:38 PM

I'm curious about the various arguments pro and con regarding voting for constitutional amendments and propositions to amend local statutes.  I realize many of the An-Cap, Minarchists, Tenthers, Constitutionalists and Libertarians have already concluded that voting for the candidates for office is pointless and is always voting for "the lesser of two evils", which is still evil.

Here in Colorado we have several proposed amendments to the state constitution that would severely limit government spending, taxation and government borrowing. (Amendments 60, 61, 101). We also have an amendment that would prohibit the state from any form of compulsory health care (Amendment 63.)

While none of these proposed changes could be considered a pure move toward a market capitalist approach, they would seem to be a move in the right direction. I'd like to hear how those representing the various sub-groups represented here might respond to such items on the local ballot.  How would Ron Paul vote? What might Murray Rothbard say? etc. 

Are there some universal principals that would help guide the decision process on such practical matters? 

All persons have certain natural, essential and inalienable rights... defending their lives and liberties; of acquiring, possessing and protecting property; and of seeking and obtaining their safety and happiness. - Constitution of the State of Colorado
Top 100 Contributor
Male
Posts 871
Points 15,025

I briefly read through the links.  The amendments are complex.  I'm not sure exactly what is to be accomplished.  Perhaps approving the amendments would be beneficial in some way, but they are so convoluted I don't know what to think. 

As a principal, voting for such things is like trying to deal with a cancer by removing only a small part of it.  It might buy some time, and make you feel like something is being accomplished, but the cancer is still there. 

"The market is a process." - Ludwig von Mises, as related by Israel Kirzner.   "Capital formation is a beautiful thing" - Chloe732.

  • | Post Points: 5
Top 200 Contributor
Male
Posts 488
Points 8,140
LeeO replied on Sun, Oct 3 2010 8:45 PM

I think it's fine to vote for the measures, as long as you make it clear that if there were an amendment to abolish the government, you'd vote for that too.

Here's what Rothbard said in chapter 30, Toward a Theory of Strategy for Liberty, of his book The Ethics of Liberty:

"If, then, the libertarian must call for immediate abolition of the State as an organized engine of aggression, and if gradualism in theory is contradictory to the overriding end (and therefore impermissible), what further strategic stance should a libertarian take in a world in which States continue all too starkly to exist? Must the libertarian necessarily confine himself to advocating immediate abolition? Are transitional demands, steps toward liberty in practice, therefore illegitimate? Surely not, since realistically there would then be no hope of achieving the final goal. It is therefore incumbent upon the libertarian, eager to achieve his goal as rapidly as possible, to push the polity ever further in the direction of that goal. Clearly, such a course is difficult, for the danger always exists of losing sight of, or even undercutting, the ultimate goal of liberty. But such a course, given the state of the world in the past, present, and foreseeable future, is vital if the victory of liberty is ever to be achieved. The transitional demands, then, must be framed while (a) always holding up the ultimate goal of liberty as the desired end of the transitional process; and (b) never taking steps, or using means, which explicitly or implicitly contradict that goal.

     Let us consider, for example, a transition demand set forth by various libertarians: namely, that the government budget be reduced by 10 percent each year for ten years, after which the government will have disappeared. Such a proposal might have heuristic or strategic value, provided that the proposers always make crystal clear that these are minimal demands, and that indeed there would be nothing wrong—in fact, it would be all to the good—to step up the pace to cutting the budget by 25 percent a year for four years, or, most desirably, by cutting it by 100 percent immediately. The danger arises in implying, directly or indirectly that any faster pace than 10 percent would be wrong or undesirable.

     An even greater danger of a similar sort is posed by the idea of many libertarians of setting forth a comprehensive and planned program of transition to total liberty, e.g., that in Year 1law A should be repealed, law B modified, tax C be cut by 20 percent, etc.; in Year 2 law D be repealed, tax C cut by a further 10 percent, etc. The comprehensive plan is far more misleading than the simple budget cut, because it strongly implies that, for example, law D should not be repealed until the second year of this planned program. Hence, the trap of philosophic gradualism, of gradualism-in-theory, would be fallen into on a massive scale. The would-be libertarian planners would be virtually falling into a position, or seeming to, of opposing a faster pace toward liberty.

     There is, indeed, another grave flaw in the idea of a comprehensive planned program toward liberty. For the very care and studied pace, the very all-embracing nature of the program, implies that the State is not really the enemy of mankind, that it is possible and desirable to use the State in engineering a planned and measured pace toward liberty. The insight that the State is the permanent enemy of mankind, on the other hand, leads to a very different strategic outlook: namely that libertarians push for and accept with alacrity any reduction of State power or State activity on any front; any such reduction at any time is a reduction in crime and aggression, and is a reduction of the parasitic malignity with which State power rules over and confiscates social power.

     For example, libertarians may well push for drastic reduction, or repeal, of the income tax; but they should never do so while at the same time advocating its replacement by a sales or other form of tax. The reduction or, better, the abolition of a tax is always a noncontradictory reduction of State power and a step toward liberty; but its replacement by a new or increased tax elsewhere does just the opposite, for it signifies a new and additional imposition of the State on some other front. The imposition of a new tax is a means that contradicts the libertarian goal itself.

     Similarly, in this age of permanent federal deficits, we are all faced with the problem: should we agree to a tax cut, even though it may well mean an increase in the deficit? Conservatives, from their particular perspective of holding budget-balancing as a higher end, invariably oppose, or vote against, a tax cut which is not strictly accompanied by an equivalent or greater cut in government expenditures. But since taxation is an evil act of aggression, any failure to welcome a tax cut with alacrity undercuts and contradicts the libertarian goal. The time to oppose government expenditures is when the budget is being considered or voted upon, when the libertarian should call for drastic slashes in expenditures as well. Government activity must be reduced whenever and wherever it can; any opposition to a particular tax—or expenditure—cut is impermissible for it contradicts libertarian principles and the libertarian goal.

     Does this mean that the libertarian may never set priorities, may not concentrate his energy on political issues which he deems of the greatest importance? Clearly not, for since everyone’s time and energy is necessarily limited, no one can devote equal time to every particular aspect of the comprehensive libertarian creed. A speaker or writer on political issues must necessarily set priorities of importance, priorities which at least partially depend on the concrete issues and circumstances of the day. Thus, while a libertarian in today’s world would certainly advocate the denationalization of lighthouses, it is highly doubtful that he would place a greater priority on the lighthouse question than on conscription or the repeal of the income tax. The libertarian must use his strategic intelligence and knowledge of the issues of the day to set his priorities of political importance. On the other hand, of course, if one were living on a small, highly fog-bound island, dependent on shipping for transportation, it could very well be that the lighthouse question would have a high priority on a libertarian political agenda. And, furthermore, if for some reason the opportunity arose for denationalizing lighthouses even in present-day America, it should certainly not be spurned by the libertarian.

     We conclude this part of the strategy question, then, by affirming that the victory of total liberty is the highest political end; that the proper groundwork for this goal is a moral passion for justice; that the end should be pursued by the speediest and most efficacious possible means; that the end must always be kept in sight and sought as rapidly as possible; and that the means taken must never contradict the goal—whether by advocating gradualism, by employing or advocating any aggression against liberty, by advocating planned programs, or by failing to seize any opportunity to reduce State power or by ever increasing it in any area."

  • | Post Points: 20
Not Ranked
Posts 28
Points 650
David replied on Sun, Oct 3 2010 10:47 PM

"As a principal, voting for such things is like trying to deal with a cancer by removing only a small part of it.  It might buy some time, and make you feel like something is being accomplished, but the cancer is still there. "

Ha! That's a great analogy.

LeeO, Thanks for the Rothbard quote. I read this great book a few months ago. As I see it, the main points in this case:

"It is therefore incumbent upon the libertarian, eager to achieve his goal as rapidly as possible, to push the polity ever further in the direction of that goal"

"But since taxation is an evil act of aggression, any failure to welcome a tax cut with alacrity undercuts and contradicts the libertarian goal."

The "Ballot Pedia" explanations from the links above seem to be a bit biased. The official ballot explanations here, seem a bit more objective.

My summary:

60 = Reduces state power by trading one form of tax that is less limited for another form of tax that is already more limited by the constitution. 

61 = Reduces state power by limiting its ability to borrow.

63 = Prevents expansion of state power in the area of health-care.

101 = Reduces state power by reducing taxes.

All persons have certain natural, essential and inalienable rights... defending their lives and liberties; of acquiring, possessing and protecting property; and of seeking and obtaining their safety and happiness. - Constitution of the State of Colorado
  • | Post Points: 5
Page 1 of 1 (4 items) | RSS